|
The Riddles of Philosophy
The World Conceptions of the Middle Ages
A foreshadowing of a new element produced by thought life itself
emerges in St. Augustine (354 430). This element soon vanishes from
the surface, however, to continue unnoticeably under the cover of
religious conception, becoming distinctly discernible again only in
the later Middle Ages. In St. Augustine, the new element appears as if
it were a reminiscence of Greek thought life. He looks into the
external world and into himself, and comes to the conclusion: May
everything else the world reveals contain nothing but uncertainty and
deception, one thing cannot be doubted, that is, the certainty of the
soul's experience itself. I do not owe this inner experience to a
perception that could deceive me; I am in it myself; it is, for
I am present when its being is attributed to it.
One can see a new element in these conceptions as against Greek
thought life, in spite of the fact that they seem at first like a
reminiscence of it. Greek thinking points toward the soul; in St.
Augustine, we are directed toward the center of the life of the soul.
The Greek thinkers contemplated the soul in its relation to the world;
in St. Augustine's approach, something in the soul life
confronts this soul life and regards it as a special, self-contained
world. One can call the center of the soul life the ego of
man. To the Greek thinkers, the relation of the soul to the world
becomes problematic, to the thinkers of modern times, that of the
ego to the soul. In St. Augustine, we have only the first
indication of this situation. The ensuing philosophical currents are
still too much occupied with the task of harmonizing world conception
and religion to become distinctly aware of the new element that has
not entered into spiritual life. But the tendency to contemplate the
riddles of the world in accordance with the demand of this new element
lives more or less unconsciously in the souls of the time that now
follows. In thinkers like Anselm of Canterbury (1033 1109)
and Thomas Aquinas (1227 1274), this tendency still shows
itself in such a way that they attribute to self-supportive thinking
the ability to investigate the processes of the world to a certain
degree, but they limit this ability. There is for them a higher
spiritual reality to which thinking, left to its own resources, can
never attain, but that must be revealed to it in a religious way. Man
is, according to Thomas Aquinas, rooted with his soul life in the
reality of the world, but this soul life cannot know this reality in
its full extent through itself alone. Man could not know how his own
being stands in the course of the world if the spirit being, to which
his knowledge does not penetrate, did not deign to reveal to him what
must remain concealed to a knowledge relying on its own power alone.
Thomas Aquinas constructs his world picture on this presupposition. It
has two parts, one of which consists of the truths that are yielded to
man's. own thought experience about the natural course of things. This
leads to a second part that contains what has come to the soul of man
through the Bible and religious revelation. Something that the soul
cannot reach by itself, if it is to feel itself in its full essence,
must therefore penetrate into the soul.
Thomas Aquinas made himself thoroughly familiar with the world
conception of Aristotle, who becomes, as it were, his master in the
life of thought. In this respect, Aquinas is, to be sure, the most
prominent, but nevertheless only one of the numerous personalities of
the Middle Ages who erect their own thought structure entirely on that
of Aristotle. For centuries, he is il maestro di color che sanno,
the master of those who know, as Dante expresses the veneration
for Aristotle in the Middle Ages. Thomas Aquinas strives to comprehend
what is humanly comprehensible in Aristotelian method. In this way,
Aristotle's world conception becomes the guide to the limit to which
the soul life can advance through its own power for him. Beyond these
boundaries lies the realm that the Greek world conception, according
to Thomas, could not reach.
Therefore, human thinking for Thomas Aquinas is in need of another
light by which it must be illuminated. He finds this light in
revelation. Whatever was to be the attitude of the ensuing thinkers
with respect to this revelation, they could no longer accept the life
of thought in the manner of the Greeks. It is not sufficient to them
that thinking comprehends the world; they make the presupposition that
it should be possible to find a basic support for thinking itself. The
tendency arises to fathom man's relation to his soul life. Thus, man
considers himself a being who exists in his soul life. If one
calls this entity the ego, one can say that in modern
times the consciousness of the ego is stirred up in man's soul
life in a way similar to that in which thought was born in the
philosophical life of the Greeks. Whatever different forms the
philosophical currents in this age assume, they all hinge on the
search for the ego-entity. This fact, however, is not always brought
clearly to the consciousness of the thinkers themselves. They mostly
believe they are concerned with questions of a different nature. One
could say that the Riddle of the Ego appears in a great variety
of masks. At times it lives in the philosophy of the thinkers in such
a concealed way that the statement that this riddle is at the bottom
of some view or other might appear as an arbitrary or forced opinion.
In the nineteenth century this struggle over the riddle of the ego
comes to its most intensive manifestation, and the world conceptions
of the present time are still profoundly engaged in this struggle.
This world riddle already lived in the conflict between the
nominalists and the realists in the Middle Ages. One can call
Anselm of Canterbury a representative of realism. For
him, the general ideas that man forms when he contemplates the world
are not mere nomenclatures that the soul produces for itself, but they
have their roots in a real life. If one forms the general idea
lion in order to designate all lions with it, it is
certainly correct to say that, for sense perception, only the
individual lions have reality. The general concept lion is
not, however, only a summary designation with significance only for
the human mind. It is rooted in a spiritual world, and the individual
lions of the world of sense perception are the various embodiments of
the one lion nature expressed in the idea of lion.
Such a reality of ideas was opposed by Nominalists like
Roscellin (also in the eleventh century). The general
ideas are only summary designations for him, names that the mind
forms for its own use for its orientation, but that do not correspond
to any reality. According to this view, only the individual things are
real. The quarrel is characteristic of the specific mentality of its
participants. Both sides feel the necessity to search for the
validity, the significance of the thoughts that the soul must produce.
Their attitude to thoughts as such is different from what the
attitudes of Plato and Aristotle were toward them. This is so because
something has happened between the end of the development of Greek
philosophy and the beginning of modern thought. Something has gone on
under the surface of historical evolution that can, however, be
observed in the attitude that the individual thinkers take with
respect to their thought life.
To the Greek thinker, thought came as a perception. It arose in the
soul as the red color appears when a man looks at a rose, and the
thinker received it as a perception. As such the thought had the
immediate power of conviction. The Greek thinker had the feeling, when
he placed himself with his soul receptively before the spiritual
world, that no incorrect thought could enter from this world into the
soul just as no perception of a winged horse could come from the sense
world as long as the sense organs were properly used. For the Greeks,
it was a question of being able to garner thoughts from the world.
They were then themselves the witnesses of their truth. The fact of
this attitude is not contradicted by the Sophists, nor is it denied by
ancient Scepticism. Both currents have an entirely different shade of
meaning in antiquity from similar tendencies in modern times. They are
not evidence against the fact that the Greek experienced thought in a
much more elementary, content-saturated, vivid and real way than it
can be experienced by the man of modern times. This vividness, which
in ancient Greece gave the character of perception to thought,
is no longer to be found in the Middle Ages.
What has happened is this. As in Greek times thought entered into the
human soul, extinguishing the formerly prevalent picture
consciousness, so, in a similar way, during the Middle Ages the
consciousness of the ego penetrated the human soul, and
this dampened the vividness of thought. The advent of the
ego-consciousness deprived thought of the strength through which it
had appeared as perception. We can only understand how the
philosophical life advances when we realize how, for Plato and
Aristotle, the thought, the idea, was something entirely different
from what it was for the personalities of the Middle Ages and modern
times. The thinker of antiquity had the feeling that thought was
given to him; the thinker of the later time had the impression
that he was producing thought. Thus, the question arises in him
as to what significance what has been produced in the soul can have
for reality. The Greek felt himself to be a soul separated from the
world; he attempted to unite with the spiritual world in thought. The
later thinker feels himself to be alone with his thought life.
Thus, the inquiry into the nature of the general ideas
begins. The thinker asks himself the questions, What is it that
I have really produced with them? Are they only rooted in me, or do
they point toward a reality?
In the period between the ancient current of philosophical life and
that of modern philosophy, the source of Greek thought life is
gradually exhausted. Under the surface, however, the human soul
experiences the approaching ego-consciousness as a fact. Since
the end of the first half of the Middle Ages, man is confronted with
this process as an accomplished fact, and under the influence of this
confrontation, new Riddles of Life emerge. Realism and
Nominalism are symptoms of the fact that man realizes the situation.
The manner in which both Realists and Nominalists speak about thought
shows that, compared to its existence in the Greek soul, it has faded
out, has been dampened as much as had been the old picture
consciousness in the soul of the Greek thinker.
This points to the dominating element that lives in the modern world
conceptions. An energy is active in them that strives beyond thought
toward a new factor of reality. This tendency of modern times cannot
be felt as the same that drove beyond thought in ancient times in
Pythagoras and later in Plotinus. These thinkers also strove beyond
thought but, according to their conception, the soul in its
development, its perfection, would have to conquer the region that
lies beyond thought. In modern times it is presupposed that the factor
of reality lying beyond thought must approach the soul, must be given
to it from without.
In the centuries that follow the age of Nominalism and Realism,
philosophical evolution turns into a search for the new reality
factor. One path among those discernible to the student of this search
is the one the medieval Mystics Meister Eckhardt (died 1327),
Johannes Tauler (died 1361), Heinrich Suso (died 1366)
have chosen for themselves. We receive the clearest idea of this path
if we inspect the so-called German Theology (Theologia,
deutsch), written by an author historically unknown. The Mystics want
to receive something into the ego-consciousness; they intend to fill
it with something. They therefore strive for an inner life that is
completely composed, surrendered in tranquillity, and that
thus patiently waits to experience the soul to be filled with the
Divine Ego. In a later time, a similar soul mood with a
greater spiritual momentum can be observed in Angelus Silesius
(1624 1677).
A different path is chosen by Nicolaus Cusanus (Nicolaus
Chrypffs, born at Kues on the Moselle, 1401, died 1464). He strives
beyond intellectually attainable knowledge to a state of soul in which
knowledge ceases and in which the soul meets its god in knowing
ignorance, in docta ignorantia. Examined superficially,
this aspiration is similar to that of Plotinus, but the soul
constitution of these two personalities is different. Plotinus is
convinced that the human soul contains more than the world of
thoughts. When it develops the energy that it possesses beyond the
power of thought, the soul becomes conscious of the state in which it
exists, and about which it is ignorant in ordinary life.
Paracelsus (1493 1541) already has the feeling with respect
to nature, which becomes more and more pronounced in the modern world
conception, that is an effect of the soul's feeling of desolation in
its ego-consciousness. He turns his attention toward the processes of
nature. As they present themselves they cannot be accepted by the soul,
but neither can thought, which in Aristotle unfolded in peaceful
communication with the events of nature, now be accepted as it appears
in the soul. It is not perceived; it is formed in the soul. Paracelsus
felt that one must not let thought itself speak; one must presuppose
that something is behind the phenomena of nature that will reveal itself
if one finds the right relationship to these phenomena. One must be
capable of receiving something from nature that one does not create
oneself as thought during the act of observation. One must be connected
with one's ego by means of a factor of reality other than
thought. A higher nature behind nature is what Paracelsus is
looking for. His mood of soul is so constituted that he does not want
to experience something in himself alone, but he means to penetrate
nature's processes with his ego in order to have revealed
to him the spirit of these processes that are under the surface of the
world of the senses. The mystics of antiquity meant to delve into the
depths of the soul; Paracelsus set out to take steps that would lead
to a contact with the roots of nature in the external world.
Jakob Boehme (1575 1624) who, as a lonely, persecuted
craftsman, formed a world picture as though out of an inner illumination,
nevertheless implants into this world picture the fundamental character
of modern times. In the solitude of his soul life he develops this
fundamental trait most impressively because the inner dualism of the
life of the soul, the contrast between the ego and the other
soul experiences, stands clearly before the eye of his spirit. He
experiences the ego as it creates an inner counterpart in
its own soul life, reflecting itself in the mirror of his own soul. He
then finds this inner experience again in the processes of the world.
In such a contemplation one finds two qualities, a good and an
evil one, which are intertwined in this world in all forces, in stars
and in elements as well as in all creatures. The evil in the world
is opposed to the good as its counterpart; it is only in the evil that
the good becomes aware of itself, as the ego becomes aware
of itself in its inner soul experiences.
|
Last Modified: 17-Jul-2009 |
The Rudolf Steiner Archive is maintained by:
The e.Librarian:
elibrarian@elib.com
|
|
|
|
|